101 occurrences of therefore etc in this volume.
[Clear Hits]

SUBSCRIBER:


past masters commons

Annotation Guide:

cover
The Ordinatio of John Duns Scotus
cover
Ordinatio. Book 4. Distinctions 14 - 42.
Book Four. Distinctions 14 - 42
Sixteenth Distinction
Question One. Whether these Three, Contrition, Confession, and Satisfaction, are the Parts of Penitence
II. To the Initial Arguments

II. To the Initial Arguments

27. To the first main argument [n.3]: it does not follow that, if a sin be simple, the avenging remedy is simple; for a legislator can justly establish that many partial penalties correspond to one sin as one integral revenge.

28. To the second [n.4] I say that when penitence, taken in the third or fourth mode [n.9], is correspondent to some sin, it can be taken in two ways:

In one way for what is of a sort to be adequately correspondent to it, and in this way a single penitence and a single penalty correspond to a single fault and, if the fault has them as parts, it is disposed to them as to integral parts.

In another way, penitence can be taken (when stated in the third or fourth way) for the general idea of what it is ‘to hold a penalty’, or to be punished for a fault, even if not adequately; and thus is it a whole universal to things that are integral parts of it in the first way. This is plain in an example. For suppose someone has killed another: there can be a just law that he be punished with a bodily punishment, and that a monetary penalty be handed over to the friends of the person killed; each of these is a penalty, and a penalty for homicide. In this way can it be called a penalty universal with respect to the monetary and bodily penalty, because each of these is the penalty, and for this sin. In another way, taking the penalty for homicide to be the total and adequate penalty for the fault, neither the bodily nor the monetary punishment is that penalty but an integral part of that penalty.

29. And it is plain how, according to this, penitence is predicated of any of these three separately [contrition, confession, satisfaction], taking them for what holds of any penalty corresponding to the fault but not totally and adequately; and it is plain how, on the other side, none of them without the other makes the penitence complete - and understand this as what is adequate to the fault.

30. To the third argument [n.5], it is plain that they [the three of contrition, confession, satisfaction] are not parts of penitence as sacrament nor of penitence as virtue, nor even parts of the act of the virtue, but they are acts commanded by the virtue, which is the proximate punitive act; and it is plain that the penalties accompanying those acts are parts of the remote effect of the act of penitence. But the elicited act of penitence could in some way be said to have those parts not formally but quasi causally, to the extent the act is in some way distinct as it commands this part and that; and in this way could they be called parts of virtue as penitence, as this inclines to inflicting all of them.

31. To the fifth argument38 [n.7] I say that of penitence as virtue and of its elicited act and of its commanded act the laborious exterior act is the fruit; and in this way must the exterior work worked be understood. And I concede that that work is not part of penitence in any of the three ways stated. It is yet part of what ‘to be punished’ is, which is the fourth among the parts enumerated before [n.9]; and it is not unacceptable that the same thing is part of something prior and fruit of something posterior.39