SUBSCRIBER:


past masters commons

Annotation Guide:

cover
The Ordinatio of John Duns Scotus
cover
Ordinatio. Book 4. Distinctions 14 - 42.
Book Four. Distinctions 14 - 42
Fifteenth Distinction
Question Two. Whether Anyone Who Has Unjustly Taken Away or Retains Another’s Property is Bound to Restore it such that He cannot be Truly Penitent without such Restitution
I. To the Question
B. How Ownerships, Distinct at the Beginning, are Justly Transferred
4. Fourth Conclusion

4. Fourth Conclusion

134. About the last type of contract, namely the giving of a loan [n.118], let the fourth conclusion of this article be as follows: for justly contracting a loan, it is necessary to keep equality in number and weight simply (with the exception of certain cases that will spoken of at the end [nn.144-150]). The reason for this is assigned by some [Thomas Aquinas, ST IIa IIae q.78 a.2 ad 2, Richard of Middleton, Sent. IV d.15 princ.5 q.5] as follows, that the use of money is its consumption, therefore he who yields it as a loan consumes it.25

135. Against this is objection made through ‘On the signification of words’, and it is today in [Boniface VIII], Sixth Book of Decretals V tit.12 ch.3, that the use of certain things is perpetually separated from ownership.26

136. It is possible, then, to assign the following reason, that in the giving of a loan ownership is transferred; for this is what the words indicate ‘I give you what is mine as loan’; therefore he who allows it as a loan does not remain owner of the loaned money, and consequently if he receives for the money something beyond the principal, he receives something for what is not his, or he sells what is not his.

137. The other reason is: let it be that the money remained his, yet the money does not of its own nature have any fruit, as some other things have that germinate from themselves; but only from someone’s industry, namely the user’s, does any fruit come. Now the industry of the user is not the industry of him who allowed the money; therefore, when he receives fruit from the money, he wishes to have the fruit of someone else’s industry, which however that other did not give him by the fact that from that other he accepted a loan exchange. And this is the reason why, by contrast, the fruit of pledges that do germinate is computed in the principal.

138. Excepted in this matter of loaning are two cases in general: for sometimes one can licitly receive more than the capital by agreement, sometimes not by agreement.

139. The first [by agreement] in three ways:

Namely by reason of conventional penalty, though however it may not be done for the fraud of usury. For example: suppose you need my money for trading, but I allow it to you up to a certain day, adding a conditional penalty that if you do not pay it on such and such a day (because I will otherwise be greatly harmed) you will pay afterwards so much more. This added penalty is licit, because it is licit for me to keep myself from damage by thus forewarning him with whom I contract. Now the sign that it is not for fraud of usury is this manifest one: when a merchant more want the money to be paid to him on a predetermined day than on the day after with added penalty; and by contrast it is for the fraud of usury when he wants the day to be missed rather than the money on that day to be paid.

The second is by reason of interest; for a debtor from whose non-payment the creditor is notably harmed, is held by justice to satisfy the creditor with interest. And although this creditor could not have an action in the external forum against the other, because for example pacts have perhaps not been entered into or have changed, yet in the forum of conscience the debtor is bound for interest beyond the principal.

The third condition is when both, namely the capital and what is superfluous, are put under uncertainty. This is proved from Gregory IX Decretals V tit. 19 ch.19, ‘On Usury’,27 and also by reason, using the argument from similarity, because just as uncertainty is an excuse there, so is it also here.

140. Also is [receiving more than the capital] licit without any agreement [n.138], because the mind alone without any verbal agreement, or other equivalent sign showing to the debtor that the lender would not lend without hope of gain, does not, when receiving more than the principal, make the lender to have what is another’s without agreement, and therefore he is not bound to restitution.

141. One needs also to understand that money has some useful use from its own nature, as for looking at or for decoration or for displaying possibility, as if one were rich, and for this end can it be rented like a horse or something rentable; and for this use can, while ownership is retained, money be received. And then is it in its totality a contract for renting or hiring (and not borrowing or lending), and a weight numerically the same should be returned, unless perhaps something equal in weight and value satisfy the renter.

142. These aforesaid rules show what is just and what unjust in exchanges immediately made, that is, when each exchanger at once gives or receives that for which he exchanges.